Skip to main content

On legislating from a Libertarian perspective

Regular readers will note that I have been struggling with Dr. Tal Scriven's Wrongness, Wisdom, and Wilderness, Toward a Libertarian Theory of Ethics and the Environment for about a week now.

It's heavy sledding: Scriven writes in that both lean and obtuse manner of modern philosophers, but the ideas beneath are very intriguing.

Scriven proposes that within the social contract for the creation of governments it is only philosophically ethical for a government to take action to prevent harm rather than to provide benefit.

[We could go around and around on what consitutes harm in this sense, which Scriven freely admits, but let that wait for a second.]

On that basis, he provides a four-point checklist that should be applied to any new law:

However, at this point we may formulate the harm principle in terms of the following conditions, which are individually necessary and jointly sufficient to justify the enforcement of a social proscription:

1. The proscription must be made reasonably clear.

2. The proscription must be capable of universal promulgation within the jurisdiction of the proscription. Morever, it must be reasonably well promulgated within that jurisdiction.

3. The type of action (or inaction) proscribed must be shown to pose a serious danger of harm.

4. The harm associated with the type of action (or inaction) proscribed must not be outweighed by the pleasures associated with that type of action (or inaction) and the harms associated with proscribing it.


Again, the burden of proving that all of these conditions obtain is on the
state, not the individual....

It should be obvious that this principle poses a test that is far more demanding than those routinely suggested by legislators' arguments even in fairly libertarian countries like the United States.


Maybe it all should be obvious, but let me try to re-state his four requirements for a law to be ethically justified under a libertarian philosophy in something approximating plain English:

1. The law must be clearly and unambiguously written.

2. The law must be universally publicized.

3. The law must prohibit an action (or an inaction) that can be demonstrated to pose serious harm to individuals.

4. The law may not be enacted if either (a) the pleasure (or good) associated with the action/inaction outweighs the harm; or (b) if prohibiting such actions/inactions creates a greater harm than leaving it alone.


Two further clarifications:

1. Scriven defines harm pretty narrowly:

Harm should include not only physical pain but also death and severe psychological suffering.


2. Action/inaction. As Scriven describes it, the definition of action would be pretty simple: bludgeoning someone to death with a hammer is an action causing harm [whether the need to cause that harm could later be justified or not].

Inaction comes from the Bad Samaritan principle, which holds that people should be held accountable for their failure to provide an easy rescue. The example Scriven uses is this: you are sitting in a chair within arm's length of a pool wherein a small child is drowning. You could easily reach out and pull the child to safety at no risk or even great inconvenience. If you do not, you have by inaction allowed harm to occur. [This is obviously a much stickier situation for many libertarians, who see potential for extensive State intervention over the definition of easy rescue, but Scriven would argue that it's still not ethical or acceptable in a Libertarian society to allow that child to drown.

While not agreeing with everything that Scriven writes, I find him to be an intriguing thinker, and I believe he is pointing the way to serious principles and discussions that the modern libertarian movement--however constituted--should be considering.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Libertarian Martin Luther King Jr. Day post

In which we travel into interesting waters . . . (for a fairly long trip, so be prepared) Dr. King's 1968 book, Where do we go from here:  chaos or community? , is profound in that it criticizes anti-poverty programs for their piecemeal approach, as John Schlosberg of the Center for a Stateless Society  [C4SS] observes: King noted that the antipoverty programs of the time “proceeded from a premise that poverty is a consequence of multiple evils,” with separate programs each dedicated to individual issues such as education and housing. Though in his view “none of these remedies in itself is unsound,” they “all have a fatal disadvantage” of being “piecemeal,” with their implementation having “fluctuated at the whims of legislative bodies” or been “entangled in bureaucratic stalling.”   The result is that “fragmentary and spasmodic reforms have failed to reach down to the profoundest needs of the poor.” Such single-issue approaches also have “another common failing — ...

More of This, Please

Or perhaps I should say, "Less of this one, please." Or how about just, "None of them. Ever again. Please....For the Love of God." Sunshine State Poll: Grayson In Trouble The latest Sunshine State/VSS poll shows controversial Democratic incumbent Alan Grayson trailing former state Senator Dan Webster by seven points, 43 percent to 36 percent. A majority of respondents -- 51 percent -- disapprove of the job that Grayson is doing. Independents have an unfavorable view of him as well, by a 36/47 margin. Grayson has ignored the conventional wisdom that a freshman should be a quiet member who carefully tends to the home fires. The latest controversy involves his " Taliban Dan " advertisement, where he explicitly compares his opponent to the Taliban, and shows a clip of Webster paraphrasing Ephesians 5:22 -- "wives, submit to your husbands." An unedited version of the clip shows that Webster was actually suggesting that husba...

A reply to Salon's R. J. Eskrow, and his 11 stupid questions about Libertarians

Posts here have been in short supply as I have been living life and trying to get a campaign off the ground. But "11 questions to see if Libertarians are hypocrites" by R. J. Eskrow, picked up at Salon , was just so freaking lame that I spent half an hour answering them. In the end (but I'll leave it to your judgment), it is not that Libertarians or Libertarian theory looks hypocritical, but that the best that can be said for Mr. Eskrow is that he doesn't have the faintest clue what he's talking about. That's ok, because even ill-informed attacks by people like this make an important point:  Libertarian ideas (as opposed to Conservative ideas, which are completely different) are making a comeback as the dynamic counterpoint to "politics as usual," and so every hack you can imagine must be dragged out to refute them. Ergo:  Mr. Eskrow's 11 questions, with answers: 1.       Are unions, political parties, elections, and ...